Are There "Human Rights" in Buddhism?
Damien
Keown
Lecturer
in Indian Religion, University of London, Goldsmiths
INTRODUCTION
In
the autumn of 1993 the Parliament of the World's Religions
met in Chicago to determine whether a consensus on basic
moral teachings could be found among the religions of
the world. The meeting was attended by representatives
of the major world religions as well as ethnic and other
minority groups. Representatives of many Buddhist schools,
including Theravaada, Mahaayaana, Vajrayaana, and Zen
were present and the main closing address was given by
the Dalai Lama in Grant Park on September 4th.
One
of the major fruits of this interfaith convention was
a document known as the Declaration
towards a Global Ethic. [1]
The Global Ethic sets out the fundamental moral
principles to which it is thought all religions subscribe.
Many of these principles concern human rights, and the
Global Ethic sees the universal recognition of
human rights and dignity by the religions of the world
as the cornerstone of a "new global order."
A
related aim of the Global Ethic was to provide
"the basis for an extensive process of discussion and
acceptance which we hope will be sparked off in all religions."
[2] The present paper is
a contribution to this process from a Buddhist perspective.
Its aims are limited to an exploration of some of the
basic issues which must be addressed if a Buddhist philosophy
of human rights is to develop. I say "develop" because
Buddhism seems to lack such a philosophy at present. Buddhism
is a latecomer to the cause of human rights, and for most
of its history has been preoccupied with other concerns.
It might be suggested, in defense of Buddhism, that concern
for human rights is a postreligious phenomenon which has
more to do with secular ideologies and power-politics
than religion, and it is therefore unreasonable to accuse
Buddhism of neglect in this area. [3]
I will suggest below that such an understanding of
human rights is mistaken, but leaving the specific issue
of human rights to one side there is no doubt that Buddhism
lags far behind religions such as Christianity and Islam
in developing the framework for a social gospel within
which questions of this kind can be addressed. For such
an intellectually dynamic tradition Buddhism is a lightweight
in moral and political philosophy. A fig-leaf of a kind
may be found in the suggestion that since much Buddhist
literature remains untranslated there may be hidden treasures
in these areas awaiting discovery. Such appeals to the
unknown, however, lack credibility. For one thing, it
would be curious if only texts on these subjects
had been lost to history while literature on all manner
of other topics abounds. Nor can it be a coincidence that
these subjects are absent from the traditional monastic
curricula. The absence of a discipline of philosophical
ethics in Indian culture as a whole makes it much more
likely that Buddhism simply invested little time in questions
of these kinds. [4]
Political
events in the course of this century, however, have forced
the issue of human rights to the top of the agenda. [5]
The Chinese invasion of Tibet, the bitter ethnic conflict
in Sri Lanka, and the experience of military dictatorship
in countries such as Burma have all provided contemporary
Buddhism with first-hand experience of the issues at stake.
Another development which has done much to focus attention
on social and political themes is the emergence of "socially
engaged Buddhism," a movement whose very name implies
a critique of the more traditional (presumably "disengaged")
forms of Buddhism. Leading Asian and Western Buddhists
now routinely express their concern about social injustice
in the Western vocabulary of human rights. What I wish
to consider here is how appropriate this language is for
Buddhism, and what grounds there are for supposing that
Buddhism is committed to the cause of "human rights" or
has any clear understanding of what the concept means.
Given the lack of intellectual effort down the centuries
in articulating, promoting and defending rights of the
kind which the world (and especially the West) is now
called upon to secure for oppressed groups like the Tibetans,
the more cynical might suggest that this late conversion
to the cause is born more of self-interest than a deep
and long-standing commitment to social justice. In calling
for respect for human rights today, then, is Buddhism
simply riding on the coat-tails of the West or is there,
after all, a commitment to human rights in Buddhist teachings?
My
theme in this paper may be summed up as the conceptual
and doctrinal basis for human rights in Buddhism. I am
concerned with the intellectual bridgework which must
be put in place if expressions of concern about human
rights are to be linked to Buddhist doctrine. There are
many aspects to this problem, but three related issues
will be considered here: the concept of rights, the concept
of human rights, and the question of how human
rights are to be grounded in Buddhist doctrine. I ask
first if the concept of "rights" is intelligible in Buddhism.
To answer this question it will be necessary to gain some
understanding of the origin of the notion in the West.
Next I ask whether the Buddhist concept of human
rights (if such a thing exists) is the same as the Western
understanding. Finally I consider in what specific area
of Buddhist teachings a doctrine of human rights might
be grounded. [6]
Since the discussion is essentially theoretical, detailed
reference will not be made to particular Buddhist cultures
or schools, to specific human rights "abuses," or to the
human rights "record" of particular regimes. [7]
Before
turning to these issues a preliminary point must be made
about Buddhism itself. In speaking of "Buddhism" I should
make clear that I am writing with reference to an abstraction
which might be termed "classical" Buddhism. This abstraction
is neither the same as nor different from Buddhism in
any historical or cultural context. It is not meant to
represent the views of any sect and is broad enough to
include both Theravaada and Mahaayaana schools. The justification
for this fiction lies in the belief that whatever concept
of human rights we regard Buddhism as holding must be
one which is universal in form. The essence of any doctrine
of human rights is its unrestricted scope, and it would
be as strange to have distinct "Theravaaada," "Tibetan"
and "Zen" doctrines of human rights as it would be to
have "Catholic," "Protestant" and "Eastern Orthodox" ones.
To insist on the priority of cultural and historical circumstances
would be tantamount to denying the validity of human rights
as a concept.
RIGHTS
The
concept of a "right" has a long intellectual history in
the West, and the contemporary notion of a right as an
exercisable power vested in or held by an individual has
its antecedents in a more impersonal understanding of
what is objectively true or right. Etymologically, the
English word "right" is derived from the Latin rectus
meaning straight. Rectus, in turn, can be traced
to the Greek orektos which means stretched out
or upright. As Richard Dagger notes, "The pattern ...
is for the notion of straightness to be extended from
the physical realm to the moral - from rectus to
rectitude, as it were." [8]
In other words, the property of a physical object,
namely that of being right, straight or upright, is applied
metaphorically in a moral context. Dagger suggests:
By
analogy with the physical sense, the primary moral sense
of "right" was a standard or measure for conduct. Something
was right - morally straight or true - if it met the
standard of rectitude, or rightness ...
Once
the idea of "rightness" had been transferred to the moral
domain, the next development was to view it as denoting
a personal entitlement of some kind. Dagger continues:
From
here the next step was to recognize that actions taken
"with right" or "by right" are taken as a matter
of right. The transition is from the belief that
I may do something because it is right, in other words,
to the belief that I may do something because I have
a right to do it ... Thus the concept of rights
joins the concept of the right. [9]
The
metaphorical moral usage of terms such as "right," "straight"
and "upright" (in opposition to "crooked," "twisted" and
"bent") readily suggests itself to the mind. The rationale
for the transition from the moral use of "right" to the
notion of a right as a personal entitlement, however,
is less obvious. Indeed, this development which took place
in the West during the late Middle Ages, and which has
been described as the "watershed" [10
] in the history of "right," may be a phenomenon
which is culturally unique. The evolution of the concept
in this direction occurs sometime between Aquinas in the
thirteenth century and the jurists Suarez and Grotius
in the seventeenth. The modern usage appears clearly in
Hobbes, writing in the middle of the seventeenth century,
and the idea of a right as a personal power occupies center
stage in political theory from this time on.
As
part of this evolution in the concept of a right the notion
of natural rights comes to prominence towards the
end of the seventeenth century, notably in the writings
of John Locke. The belief that there are natural rights
flows from the recognition of human equality, one of the
great ideals of the Age of Revolution. Natural rights
are inalienable: they are not conferred by any judicial
or political process nor can they be removed by these
or other means. These natural rights of the seventeenth
and eighteenth centuries are the forerunner of the contemporary
notion of human rights.
Two
questions might be asked concerning the evolution of the
doctrine of natural rights in the West. First, why did
it take so long for the concept of natural rights to appear?
The answer seems to lie in the fact that for much of Western
history "rights" were closely tied to social status, and
were essentially a function of position or role in society.
A hierarchical social structure, such as was predominant
in Roman and medieval society, is antithetical to the
notion of natural rights. In these circumstances a person's
duties and responsibilities are determined fundamentally
by the office they hold (lord, citizen, slave), offices
which are to a large extent hereditary. It was only when
the hierarchical model was challenged and replaced by
an egalitarian one that the idea of natural rights began
to gain ground.
The
second and more important question for our present purposes
is: Does the part played by the unique cultural matrix
of social political and intellectual developments in the
Enlightenment mean that human rights are essentially a
function of the historical process? This conclusion need
not follow, for while it may be said that in the seventeenth
and eighteenth centuries the notion of natural rights
was "an idea whose time had come," the idea itself was
not entirely new. The influence of Christian doctrine
can be seen in several respects, [11]
such as the belief (ultimately derived from Judaism)
of a "universal moral law rooted in the righteousness
of God." [12] Since
human beings are created in the image of God and loved
by him as individuals each is worthy of dignity and respect.
Furthermore, since each is a member of the human community
under God, all other memberships (tribe, state, nation)
are secondary.[13] Apart
from Christianity, ideas about the just treatment of individuals
on the basis of their common humanity are found in a secular
context in Stoicism and the writings of Cicero and Seneca. [14]
The philosophical justification for a doctrine
of human rights has thus always been available, although
the ground in which this seed might flourish - a particular
combination of social, political and intellectual developments
- has not.
So
much for historical background. What of contemporary theories
of rights? The concept of a right has been analyzed in
a number of ways, as evidenced by the extensive interdisciplinary
literature on the subject spanning diverse fields such
as politics, law, philosophy and history. Within this
discourse of rights there is no single definition of a
right which commands universal assent. For our present
purposes, however, a basic understanding of the concept
will suffice. We noted above that a right is something
personal to an individual: it may be thought of as something
an individual has. [15]
What the holder of a right has is a benefit
or entitlement of some kind, and at the most general level
this is an entitlement to justice. This entitlement may
be analyzed into two main forms for which there are corresponding
rights: rights which take the form of a claim (claim-rights),
and rights which take the form of a liberty (liberty-
rights).[16] A claim-right
is the benefit which A enjoys to impose upon B a positive
or negative requirement. A liberty-right is the
benefit which A enjoys of being immune from any such requirement
being imposed by B. [17]
This basic understanding of a right may be summed
up in the following working definition: a right is
a benefit which confers upon its holder either a claim
or a liberty. One important feature of any right is
that it provides a particular perspective on justice,
in that the right-holder always stands in the position
of beneficiary. This subjective aspect of the entitlement,
which, as we have seen, appeared early in the history
of the concept, remains crucial to the modern understanding
of a right. This is brought out in the following definition
by Finnis:
In
short, the modern vocabulary and grammar of rights is
a many-faceted instrument for reporting and asserting
the requirements or other implications of a relationship
of justice from the point of view of the person(s)
who benefit(s) from that relationship. It provides
a way of talking about "what is just" from a special
angle: the viewpoint of the "other(s)" to whom something
(including, inter alia, freedom of choice) is
owed or due, and who would be wronged if denied that
something. [18]
The
above brief review of the Western concept of a right was
required as a preliminary to an assessment of its relevance
to Buddhism. We are now in a position to ask whether the
concept of a right is found in Buddhism. If it is, then
talk of human rights in Buddhism seems legitimate.[19]
If it is not, there is a danger of anachronistically
foisting onto the tradition a concept which is the product
of an alien culture. [20]
BUDDHISM
AND RIGHTS
We
took our cue for the discussion of rights in the West
from etymology, and perhaps we can glean something further
from this source. Above it was noted that the English
word "right" is derived from the Latin rectus meaning
straight. Both "right" and rectus themselves, however,
have a more remote ancestor in the Sanskrit rju
(straight or upright). The equivalent form in Pali is
uju (or ujju) meaning "straight, direct;
straightforward, honest, upright." [21]
It would therefore appear that both the objective
sense ("straight") and the metaphorical moral sense ("rectitude")
of the word "right" referred to earlier occur in Buddhist
as well as Western languages. Despite a common Indo-European
etymology, however, there is no word in Sanskrit or Pali
which conveys the idea of a "right" or "rights," understood
as a subjective entitlement. [22]
Does
this mean that the concept of rights is alien to Buddhist
thought? Not necessarily. Alan Gewirth has pointed out
that cultures may possess the concept of rights without
having a vocabulary which expresses it. He suggests that
it is "important to distinguish between having or using
a concept and the clear or explicit recognition and elucidation
of it ... Thus persons might have and use the concept
of a right without explicitly having a single word for
it."[23] Gewirth
claims that the concept of rights can be found in feudal
thought, Roman law, Greek philosophy, the Old Testament,
and in primitive societies. In connection with the last
Finnis points out that anthropological studies of African
tribal regimes of law have shown that "the English terms
a 'right' and 'duty' are usually covered by a single word
derived from the form normally translated as 'ought.'"
He suggests that the best English translation in these
cases is "due" because "'due' looks both ways along a
juridical relationship, both to what one is due to do,
and to what is due to one." [24]
It
seems, then, that the concept of a right may exist where
a word for it does not. Could this be the case in Buddhism?
In Buddhism what is due in any situation is determined
by reference to Dharma. Dharma determines what is right
and just in all contexts and from all perspectives. With
respect to social justice the Rev. Vajiragnana explains:
Each
one of us has a role to play in sustaining and promoting
social justice and orderliness. The Buddha explained
very clearly these roles as reciprocal duties existing
between parents and children; teachers and pupils; husband
and wife; friends, relatives and neighbors; employer
and employee; clergy and laity ... No one has been left
out. The duties explained here are reciprocal and are
considered as sacred duties, for - if observed - they
can create a just, peaceful and harmonious society. [25]
From
this it would seem that Dharma determines not just "what
one is due to do" but also "what is due to one." Thus
through A's performance of his Dharmic duty B receives
that which is his "due" or, we might say, that to which
he is "entitled" in (under, through) Dharma. Since Dharma
determines the duties of husbands and the duties of wives, [26]
it follows that the duties of one correspond to the entitlements
or "rights" of the other. If the husband has a duty to
support his wife, the wife has a "right" to support from
her husband. If the wife has a duty to look after her
husband's property, the husband has a "right" to the safe-keeping
of his property by his wife. If under Dharma it is the
duty of a king (or political authority) to dispense justice
impartially, then subjects (citizens) may be said to have
a "right" to just and impartial treatment before the law.
Should
it be concluded, then, that the notion of a right is present
in classical Buddhism? The answer depends on the criteria
adopted for "having" a concept. Dagger sets out the options:
If
one is willing to look primarily for the idea or the
notion, however it may be expressed, then one can confidently
say that the concept of rights is virtually as old as
civilization itself.
On
the other hand:
If
one insists that the form of expression is crucial ...
so that a concept cannot be said to exist unless there
is a word or phrase that distinguishes it from other
concepts, then one would have to say that the concept
of rights has its origin in the middle ages. [27]
I
think our conclusion should be that the concept of rights
is implicit in classical Buddhism in the normative understanding
of what is "due" among and between individuals. Under
Dharma, husbands and wives, kings and subjects, teachers
and students, all have reciprocal obligations which can
be analyzed into rights and duties. We must qualify this
conclusion, however, by noting that the requirements of
Dharma are expressed in the form of duties rather than
rights. In other words, Dharma states what is due in the
form "A husband should support his wife" as opposed to
"Wives have a right to be maintained by their husbands."
Until rights as personal entitlements are recognized as
a discrete but integral part of what is due under Dharma,
the modern concept of rights cannot be said to be present.
In this respect, however, Buddhism is far from unique,
and a similar comment could be made about many other cultures
and civilizations. Finnis points out with respect to Roman
law:
[I]t
is salutary to bear in mind that the modern emphasis
on the powers of the right-holder, and the consequent
systematic bifurcation between "right" ... and "duty",
is something that sophisticated lawyers were able to
do without for the whole life of classical Roman law. [28]
He
also suggests, rightly I think, that "there is no cause
to take sides as between the older and the newer usages,
as ways of expressing the implications of justice in a
given context." [29]
A right is a useful concept which provides a particular
perspective on justice. Its correlative, duty, provides
another. These may be thought of as separate windows onto
the common good which is justice or, in the context of
Buddhism, Dharma. It would therefore be going too far
to claim that the notion of rights is "alien" to Buddhism
or that Buddhism denies that individuals have "rights."
In
sum it might be said that in classical Buddhism the notion
of rights is present in embryonic form although not yet
born into history. Whether anything like the Western concept
of rights has, or would, appear in the course of the historical
evolution of Buddhism is a question for specialists in
the various Buddhist cultures to ponder. In many respects
the omens for this development were never good. Buddhism
originated in a caste society, and the Asian societies
where it has flourished have for the most part been hierarchically
structured. MacIntyre, citing Gewirth, mentions that the
concept of a right lacks any means of expression in Japanese
"even as late as the mid-nineteenth century." [30]
The preconditions for the emergence of the concept
of rights would seem to be egalitarianism and democracy,
neither of which have been notable features of Asian polity
before the modern era. On the other hand, a justification
for the rejection of hierarchical social structures is
not hard to find in Buddhism - one need look only at the
Buddha's critique of caste. [31]
Buddhism also holds, in the doctrine of no-self, that
all individuals are equal in the most profound sense. [32]
Like the Christian doctrine that all men are created
equal before God this would appear to be fertile ground
for a doctrine of natural rights. What seems to have been
lacking in both faiths, but perhaps more so in Buddhism,
was the will to incarnate this theoretical vision of man
in the flesh of historical institutions.
HUMAN
RIGHTS
In
the preceding section attention was focused on the concept
of a right. Here we consider what it means to characterize
certain rights as human rights, [33]
and pursue further the discussion initiated in the
preceding section as to whether Western notions of human
rights are compatible with Buddhism. [34]
The
point has already been made that what are today called
human rights were originally spoken of as "natural" rights,
in other words, rights which flow from human nature.
In the seventeenth century philosophers and statesmen
began to define these rights and enshrine them in early
constitutions such as the Fundamental
Orders of Connecticut as early as 1639. Documents
of this kind inspired the publication of other declarations,
charters and manifestos in a tradition which has continued
into modern times. As an example of a modern charter of
human rights we may take The
Universal Declaration of Human Rights proclaimed by
the General Assembly of the United Nations in December
1948. Since its promulgation this thirty- article code
has been used as a model for many subsequent human rights
charters.
What
is the Buddhist position with respect to declarations
of this kind? It may be useful to begin by asking whether
Buddhism would endorse the Universal Declaration of Human
Rights. The repeated calls by the Dalai Lama for respect
for human rights give some reason to think that it would.
The signing of the Global Ethic by many Buddhists
also suggests that Buddhism has no reservations about
subscribing to charters or manifestos which seek to secure
universal human rights. Moreover, there seems to be nothing
in any of the thirty articles to which Buddhism would
take exception. Perera's commentary on each of the thirty
articles of the Universal Declaration shows them to be
in harmony with early Buddhist teachings both in letter
and in spirit. In his Foreword to the commentary
Ananda Gurugeí writes:
Professor
Perera demonstrates that every single Article of the
Universal Declaration of Human Rights - even the labour
rights to fair wages, leisure and welfare - has been
adumbrated, cogently upheld and meaningfully incorporated
in an overall view of life and society by the Buddha. [35]
But
how are these rights to be justified with reference to
Buddhist teachings? In asking this question I am not seeking
justification by reference to textual passages which seem
to support the rights claimed. There are many passages
in the Pali Canon, as Perera has ably demonstrated, which
support the view that early Buddhist teachings were in
harmony with the spirit of the Declaration. The justification
required at this point has more to do with the philosophical
presuppositions underlying these passages and the overall
Buddhist vision of individual and social good.
The
various declarations on human rights themselves rarely
offer a justification for the rights they proclaim. MacIntyre
observes dryly how "In the United Nations declaration
on human rights of 1949 [sic] what has
since become the normal UN practice of not giving good
reasons for any assertion whatsoever is followed with
great rigor." [36]
A gesture towards justification is sometimes made
in recital clauses by reference to the "inherent dignity
... of all members of the human family" or some similar
form of words. The Global Ethic, which provides
a fuller statement than most, echoes the Universal Declaration
in its call for "the full realization of the intrinsic
dignity of the human person". [37]
It states: "We make a commitment to respect life and
dignity, individuality and diversity, so that every person
is treated humanely." This is amplified as follows:
This
means that every human being without distinction of
age, sex, race, skin, color, physical or mental ability,
language, religion, political view, or national or social
origin possesses an inalienable and untouchable dignity.
And everyone, the individual as well as the state, is
therefore obliged to honor this dignity and protect
it. [38]
Elsewhere,
as part of his dialogue with world religions, Kung makes
a constructive suggestion on this point that students
of Buddhism might do well to pay heed to:
Should
not Buddhist thinkers, as they critically assess their
own and alien traditions, make a more direct effort
to establish an anthropology centered around human
dignity (which the Buddha himself deeply respected)?
Buddhists are fully aware that man can be adequately
understood only as conditioned in every way, as a relational
being within the totality of life and the cosmos. But
should they not reflect more earnestly, especially in
an ethical vein, on the problems of the unique, inviolable,
noninterchangeable human self, with its roots in the
past and its future destiny? [39]
It
is by no means apparent, however, how human dignity is
to be grounded in Buddhist doctrine. The very words "human
dignity" sound as alien in a Buddhist context as talk
of rights. One looks in vain to the The Four Noble Truths
for any explicit reference to human dignity, and doctrines
such as no-self and impermanence may even be thought to
undermine it. If human dignity is the basis of human rights
Buddhism would seem to be in some difficulty when it comes
to providing a justification for them. The theistic religions,
on the other hand, seem much better equipped to provide
an account of human dignity. Christians, Muslims and Jews
typically refer to the ultimate source of human dignity
as divine. Article one (paragraph 1700) of the most recent
Catechism of the Catholic Church, for instance,
states: "The dignity of the human person is rooted in
his creation in the image and likeness of God." Buddhism,
clearly, would not wish to make such a claim. Kung notes
how leading Buddhists at the Parliament of the World's
Religions felt called upon to protest at calls for "a
unity of religions under God," and at references to "God
the Almighty" and "God the Creator" in invocations during
the proceedings. He suggests, however, that these differences
are reconcilable since the Buddhist concepts of "Nirvana,
Shunyata and Dharmakaya ... fulfil analogous functions
to the concept of God" and can be regarded by Christians
as "parallel terms for the Absolute." [40]
It
may or may not be the case that Mahaayaana schools recognize
a transcendent reality which resembles the Christian concept
of God as the Absolute, and there are those better qualified
than myself to address such a question. Here I will make
only three brief points regarding the problems which arise
in regarding these things as the source of human dignity.
The first is that since these concepts are understood
differently by the main Mahaayaana schools they are unlikely
to provide the common ground which is required as a foundation
for human rights. The second is that it is difficult to
see how any of these things can be the source of human
dignity in the way that God can, since no school of Buddhism
believes that human beings are created by them. The third
point is that even if some metaphysical ground of the
above kind can be identified in Mahaayaana Buddhism it
still leaves the problem of how human dignity is to be
grounded where Theravaada Buddhism is concerned. For the
Theravaada, Nirvaa.na is not a transcendent Absolute,
nor do the concepts of "Shunyata and Dharmakaya" have
anything like the meaning or significance they attain
later. No grounding for human rights can be truly satisfactory,
I would suggest, unless it unambiguously forms part of
the core teachings of classical Buddhism as a whole.
One
suggestion as to how human rights can be grounded in Buddhist
doctrine has been made by Kenneth Inada. In a discussion
of "The Buddhist Perspective on Human Rights," Inada suggests
"there is an intimate and vital relationship of the Buddhist
norm or Dhamma with that of human rights." [41]
He explains the relationship as follows:
Human
rights is indeed an important issue, but the Buddhist
position is that it is ancillary to the larger or more
basic issue of human nature. It can be asserted that
the Buddhist sees the concept of human rights as a legal
extension of human nature. It is a crystallization,
indeed a formalization, of the mutual respect and concern
of all persons, stemming from human nature. Thus, human
nature is the ultimate source, the basis from which
all other attributes or characteristics are to be delineated.
They all have their respective raison d'etre
in it. They are reflections and even byproducts of it.
The reason for assigning human nature the basic position
is very simple. It is to give human relations a firm
grounding in the truly existential nature of things:
that is, the concrete and dynamic relational nature
of persons in contact with each other, that which [sic]
avoids being caught up in rhetorical or legalistic tangles. [42]
Few
would disagree with the proposition that human rights
are grounded in human nature. Towards the end of the extract,
however, Inada seems to move away from his initial suggestion
that human nature is the "ultimate source" of human
rights towards the view that the ultimate ground is the
"dynamic relational nature of persons in contact with
each other." In other words, it is in the interrelatedness
of persons rather than in the persons themselves that
the justification for human rights is to be found. This
is confirmed a little later:
Consequently,
the Buddhist concern is focused on the experiential
process of each individual, a process technically know
as relational origination (pa.ticca-samuppaada).
It is the great doctrine of Buddhism, perhaps the greatest
doctrine expounded by the historical Buddha. It means
that, in any life-process, the arising of an experiential
event is a total, relational affair. [43]
How
is the link between dependent-origination and human rights
to be forged? The argument reaches its conclusion in the
following passage:
Like
a storm which consumes everything in its wake, an experience
in terms of relational origination involves everything
within its purview. Hence, the involvement of elements
and, in our case, human beings as entities should not
be in terms of mere relationship but rather a creative
relationship which originates from the individual locus
of existence. In other words, each individual is responsible
for the actualization of an "extensive concern" for
everything that lies in his or her path of experience.
So, we may say that the sum total of the "extensive
concerns" can be referred to as a mutually constituted
existential realm, and it thereby becomes a fact that
there will be mutual respect of fellow beings. It is
on this basis that we can speak of the rights of individuals.
These rights are actually extensions of human qualities
such as security, liberty, and life. [44]
In
simple language, the argument seems to be as follows.
Human beings, like everything else, are part of the relational
process described in the doctrine of dependent-origination;
since no-one exists independently we should look out for
one another; looking out for one another means respecting
each other's rights; examples of the rights we should
respect are security, liberty and life. [45]
Although
I have described this as an "argument" it is little more
than a series of assertions. Working backwards, it is
difficult to know what sense to give the concluding sentence:
"These rights are actually extensions of human qualities
such as security, liberty and life." It is unclear what
is meant by "human qualities" here. In what sense is security
a "human quality" (perhaps a "need")? Why is life described
as a "quality" of a human being? Even granted that these
things are "human qualities," what does it mean to say
that rights are extensions of "human qualities"? In the
first extract quoted above, Inada suggests that "the Buddhist
sees the concept of human rights as a legal extension
of human nature." What is left unexplained, however, is
how human nature (or "human qualities") become legal rights.
Do all "human qualities" extend into rights or only some?
If so, which and why? Finally, if "human qualities" are
what give rise to rights, why invoke the doctrine of dependent-
origination?
The
derivation of human rights from the doctrine of dependent-origination
is a conjuring trick. From the premise that we live in
"a mutually constituted existential realm" (we all live
together) it has "thereby become a fact" that there will
be "mutual respect of fellow beings." In the twinkling
of an eye, values have appeared from facts like a rabbit
out of a hat. However, the fact that human beings live
in relationship with one another is not a moral argument
about how they ought to behave. By itself it offers
no reason why a person should not routinely abuse the
rights of others. Inada's suggestion that human rights
can be grounded in the doctrine of dependent- origination
turns out to be little more than a recommendation that
people should be nice to one another on the ground that
we are "all in this together." [46]
The
approach adopted by Perera is rather different. Perera's
main concern is to demonstrate that the articles of the
Universal Declaration are adumbrated in early Buddhist
teachings, rather than explore their philosophical foundations.
He acknowledges that "Buddhism credits the human personality
with a dignity and moral responsibility" [47]
but does not explain fully whence this arises or how
it provides a foundation for human rights. In a number
of places he suggests certain possibilities regarding
the source of human dignity, not all of which seem to
be compatible. At one point he defines "the ethical assumption
on which the Buddhist concept of human rights is founded"
as the "fundamental consideration that all life has a
desire to safeguard itself and to make itself comfortable
and happy." [48]
Basing rights on desires, however, is problematic.
One reason is that certain people, for example those who
seek to end their lives through suicide, seem to lack
the desire in question. Nor is difficult to conceive of
a justification for human rights abuses along the lines
that the victims "no longer cared what happened to them."
If they themselves had no interest in their future, whose
rights would have been violated? A deeper problem is that
the mere existence of desires establishes nothing from
a moral point of view. Desires are many and varied
and can be met in manifold ways. Moral questions arise
both at the level of whether a desire should be
met and how it should be met. The identification of a
desire may be a starting point for moral reflection, but
it is certainly not its end. [49]
On
the preceding page Perera suggests an alternative foundation
for human rights, one which links it to human dignity.
He writes: "Buddhism posits, as Jean Jaques Rousseau did
much later, that the essence of human dignity lies in
the assumption of man's responsibility for his own governance." [50]
No Buddhist sources are cited in support of this claim,
and I believe it is unlikely that Buddhism would wish
to link human dignity quite so closely to politics. Perhaps
if this suggestion were developed a little further it
would make reference to underlying human capacities such
as reason and autonomy which enable men to constitute
themselves into orderly societies, and then point to these
as the underlying source of human dignity. While political
institutions may be produced through the exercise of distinctively
human capacities, however, it is unlikely that Buddhism
would locate "the essence of human dignity" in their creation.
According to the Agga~~nnasutta, the evolution
of political societies is the consequence of depravity
and decline, which makes them a dubious testament to human
dignity. Where then, should the foundations for a Buddhist
doctrine of human rights be sought? The proper ground
for a doctrine of human rights, I suggest, lies elsewhere
than in the doctrine of dependent-origination, as suggested
by Inada, or in either the desire for self- preservation
or the acceptance of responsibility for self-government,
as proposed by Perera. Perera, in fact, comes closest
to what in my view is the true source of human rights
in Buddhism in his commentary on Article 1.[51]
In discussing the first sentence of the Article ("All
human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights")
he comments that "Buddhahood itself is within the reach
of all human beings ... and if all could attain Buddhahood
what greater equality in dignity and rights can there
be?" To focus attention upon the goal, I believe, is more
promising than any of the other approaches considered
thus far. Perera seems to grasp its significance in a
remark towards the end of his commentary on Article 1.
He writes:
It
is from the point of view of its goal that Buddhism
evaluates all action. Hence Buddhist thought is in accord
with this and other Articles in the Universal Declaration
of Human Rights to the extent to which they facilitate
the advancement of human beings towards the Buddhist
goal. [52]
I
believe the above statement provides the key to understanding
human rights from a Buddhist perspective. What is missing
in Perera's commentary, however, is the explicit linkage
between the goal and human dignity, and it is this which
I will now try to establish. What I will suggest in general
is that the source of human dignity should be sought not
in the analysis of the human condition provided by the
first and second noble truths (the area where Buddhist
scholarship has myopically focused its attention) but
in the evaluation of human good provided by the third
and fourth. Human rights cannot be derived from any factual
non-evaluative analysis of human nature, whether in terms
of its psycho-physical constitution (the five "aggregates"
which lack a self), its biological nature (needs, urges,
drives), or the deep structure of interdependency (pa.ticca-samupaada)
. Instead, the most promising approach will be one which
locates human rights and dignity within a comprehensive
account of human goodness, and which sees basic rights
and freedoms as integrally related to human flourishing
and self-realization. [53]
This is because the source of human dignity in Buddhism
lies nowhere else than in the literally infinite capacity
of human nature for participation in goodness. [54]
The
connection between human rights and human good can be
illustrated by asking what the various declarations on
human rights see to secure. Documents which speak of human
rights commonly announce a list of specific rights and
freedoms and proclaim them to be inviolable. The rights
proclaimed by the Universal Declaration include the right
to life, liberty, security of person, equality before
the law, privacy, marriage and protection of family life,
social security, participation in government, work, protection
against unemployment, rest and leisure, a minimum standard
of living, and enjoyment of the arts. The exercise of
these rights is subject only to such general limitations
as are necessary to secure due recognition and respect
for the rights and freedoms of others and the requirements
of morality, public order and general welfare (Article
29.2). Otherwise, the rights are expressed in categorical
forms such as "Everyone has ..." and "No-one shall ...".
For example, Article 3: "Everyone has the right to life,
liberty and security of person." And Article 4: "No one
shall be held in slavery or servitude; slavery and the
slave trade shall be prohibited in all their forms." The
document thus understands the rights it proclaims as both
"universal" and exceptionless. Using the terminology introduced
earlier it can be seen that some of these rights are claim
rights while others are liberty rights. Article 2 confirms
this when it speaks of an entitlement to both the "rights
and freedoms set forth in this Declaration." [55]
What
do these rights and freedoms amount to? It might be said
that they map the parameters of human "good-in-community."
In other words, these rights and freedoms are what is
required if human beings are to lead fulfilled lives in
society. Article 29.1 recognizes this when it observes
"Everyone has duties to the community in which alone
the free and full development of his personality is possible."[56]
In the absence of human rights the scope for human development
and fulfillment through social interaction is drastically
reduced. The rights specified define and facilitate aspects
of human fulfillment. The right to life is clearly fundamental
since it is the condition for the enjoyment of all other
rights and freedoms. The right to "liberty and security
of person" (Article 3) is also basic to any understanding
of human good. Without these minimum conditions the scope
and opportunity for human fulfillment would be intolerably
restricted. The same would apply in the case of slavery
(Article 4), torture (Article 5), and the denial of rights
before the law (Article 6). It can also be seen that many
of the detailed rights identified are actually derived
from more fundamental ones. Article 3, for example, "No
one shall be held in slavery," is clearly implied in Article
2, "Everyone has the right to ... liberty." It might thus
be said that many of the thirty articles articulate the
practical implications of a relatively small number of
fundamental rights and freedoms which are the basis of
the common good.
It
may be noted that the Universal Declaration itself and
modern charters like it do not offer a comprehensive
vision of human good. This is not intended as a criticism,
for the purpose of such charters is to secure only what
might be termed the "minimum conditions" for human flourishing
in a pluralistic milieu. The task of articulating a comprehensive
vision of what is ultimately valuable in human life and
how it is to be attained falls to the competing theories
of human good found in religions, philosophies and ideologies.
Buddhism provides one view of human nature and its fulfillment,
Christianity another, secular philosophies a third. To
pursue any of these different paths, however, requires
the substructure known as "human rights," a complex of
fundamental rights and liberties which are the preconditions
for the realization of the particular opportunities made
available by the competing ideologies.
If
the aim of human rights declarations is understood in
the way outlined above then human rights is fundamentally
a moral issue. Where there is no right to life, liberty
and security of person, and where torture is routine,
the opportunities for the realization of human good are
greatly reduced. Freedom of religion (Article 18), for
example, is vital to the Buddhist vision of individual
and social good, and the consequences of the loss of these
rights are all too obvious in Tibet. Human rights is thus
an area in which religions have a legitimate and vital
stake, and there is every reason why it would be proper
for Buddhism both to endorse the Universal Declaration
and call upon others to respect and implement it. [57]
If
religions have a legitimate stake in human rights, we
might expect to find many of the rights and liberties
spelled out in human rights charters present in either
an express or implied form in their moral teachings. These
typically include commandments or precepts forbidding
killing, stealing, adultery, and lying, as do the first
four of the Five Precepts. These evils are prohibited
because it is immediately apparent that they are antithetical
to human flourishing-in-community. The rationale for these
prohibitions, I suggest, coincides to a large extent with
that of the various human rights manifestos. [58]
These manifestos, indeed, may be regarded as a translation
of religious precepts into the language of rights. The
process of casuistry can be seen at work in both. Just
as a limited number of moral precepts can be expanded
to meet the needs of different social situations (many
of the extensive Vinaya rules, for example, have their
source in a handful of moral precepts), [59]
so the many articles in human rights charters are
extrapolated from a comparatively small number of basic
rights and freedoms.
It
must be admitted there are grounds for skepticism towards
the parallel which has just been suggested since it cannot
be denied that the Buddhist precepts look and sound very
different from contemporary declarations on human rights.
The Buddhist precepts make no reference to "rights" at
all, and are couched instead in the form of undertakings. [60]
Let us examine what these undertakings involve. On
the basis of our earlier analysis it would seem that "taking
the precepts" in Buddhism is actually the formal acknowledgment
of a subsisting duty, a duty which arises from Dharma.
The person who takes the precepts is saying in effect
"I hereby recognize my Dharmic duty not to do x,y, and
z." Since duties have their correlative in rights, however,
rights must also be implicit in the good the precepts
seek to promote. We saw earlier that rights provide a
way of talking about what is just and unjust from a special
angle. We noted further that a person who has right has
a benefit, a benefit which can be described as either
a claim or a liberty. In the context of the precepts,
then, the right-holder is the one who suffers from the
breach of Dharmic duty when the precepts are broken. In
the case of the first precept this would be the person
who was unjustly killed. The right the victim has may
therefore be defined as a negative claim-right upon the
aggressor, namely the right not to be killed. In simple
terms we might say that the victim has a right to life
which the aggressor has a duty to respect.
That
the translation between precepts and rights is accurate,
and that the agreement between the two formulations is
more than superficial or accidental, is supported by the
authenticity with which the Dalai Lama was able to affirm
the Global Ethic. Kuschel comments as follows:
Something
else seems decisive to me: authenticity and humanity.
The reason why the Dalai Lama's speech was so convincing,
and indeed seized people's hearts, so that it was often
interrupted by spontaneous applause, was that this man
simply wanted to be an authentic Buddhist. His
plea for mutual respect, dialogue and collaboration,
for understanding between peoples and respect for creation,
was not an adaptation to Christian or Western values,
but came from the depths of his own Buddhist spirituality. [61]
Further
evidence of the linkage between the Buddhist precepts
and social justice is found in the Theravaada tradition.
Writing on the theme of "Justice in Buddhism" Vajiragnana
states:
Man
is responsible for society. It is he who makes it good
or bad through his own actions. Buddhism, therefore,
advocates a five-fold disciplinary code for man's training
in order to maintain justice in society ... These five
... precepts are extremely important fundamental principles
for promoting and perpetuating human welfare, peace
and justice. [62]
I
suggest, then, that the apparent differences between the
moral teachings of Buddhism and human rights charters
is one of form rather than substance. Human rights can
be extrapolated from Buddhist moral teachings in the manner
described above using the logic of moral relationships
to illumine what is due under Dharma. A direct translation
of the first four precepts yields a right to life, a right
not to have one's property stolen, a right to fidelity
in marriage, and a right not to be lied to. Many other
human rights, such as the rights to liberty and security
can either be deduced from or are extant within the general
corpus of Buddhist moral teachings. A right not to be
held in slavery, for example, is implicit in the canonical
prohibition on trade in living beings. [63]
These rights are the extrapolation of what is due
under Dharma; they have not been "imported" into Buddhism
but were implicitly present.
If
modern conceptions of human rights and Buddhist moral
teachings are related in the way I have suggested, certain
conclusions follow for our understanding of the Buddhist
precepts. If there are universal and exceptionless rights,
as human rights charters affirm, there must be universal
and exceptionless duties. If human rights such as a "right
to life" (by which I understand a right not to have one's
life taken unjustly) are exceptionless, there must also
be an exceptionless duty to abstain from unjustly depriving
a human being of life. The First Precept in Buddhism,
therefore, should be understood as an exceptionless duty
or moral absolute.
Is
this reverse translation, from absolute human rights to
absolute moral duties, supported by textual sources? There
is every reason to think that it is. Such an understanding
of the precept is clearly evident in classical Buddhism,
which tirelessly reiterates the principle of the sanctity
of life found in the pan- Indian teachings on non-harming
(ahi.msaa), and which gives no reason to suppose
that its moral precepts are to be understood as anything
other than exceptionless norms. If, on the other hand,
it is thought that the precepts are not to be understood
as moral absolutes, then it is difficult to see what justification
there can be for Buddhists to hold that there are universal
and exceptionless human rights. It would be inconsistent
to affirm the latter but deny the former.
The
above account of human rights in Buddhism has been given
entirely within the context of an understanding of human
good which has its apex in nirvana-in-this-life. Reference
to the transcendent dimension of human good and its ground
has been avoided for several reasons. The first is that
no reference need be made to transcendent realities in
order to ground human rights. That this is so can be seen
from the absence of any reference to such realities in
contemporary human rights charters, and the fact that
many atheists are vigorous defenders of human rights.
Where Buddhism is concerned, the vision of human good
set out in the third and fourth noble truths provides
the necessary basis for a doctrine of human rights. Human
rights turn out in essence to be what justice requires
if human good is to be fulfilled. The second reason for
avoiding reference to transcendent realities is that my
aim has been to suggest a basis for human rights acceptable
to classical Buddhism as a whole. Since all schools of
Buddhism affirm the third and fourth noble truths and
the vision of human good they proclaim, the required common
ground for a pan-Buddhist doctrine of human rights is
present.
The
above should not be read as a denial that there
can be a transcendent ground for human rights in Buddhism.
Because the transcendent dimension of human good is left
obscure in Buddhist teachings, however, the transcendent
ground for human rights is also obscure. In terms of the
account given here, the transcendent ground for human
rights would be post-mortem nirvana, not in the sense
of an absolute reality (as suggested by Kung) but as the
universalization of human good on a transcendent plane.
The twin axes of human good are knowledge (praj~naa)
and moral concern (karu.naa) and on the graph defined
by these axes can be plotted the soteriological coordinates
of any individual. Through participation in these twin
categories of good, human nature progressively transcends
its limitations and becomes saturated with nirvanic goodness.
Eventually, in post-mortem nirvaa.na, this goodness attains
a magnitude which can no longer be charted. If a transcendent
ground for human rights is desired, this is where it should
be sought.
To
sum up: it is legitimate to speak of both rights and human
rights in Buddhism. Modern doctrines of human rights are
in harmony with the moral values of classical Buddhism
in that they are an explication of what is "due" under
Dharma. The modern idea of human rights has a distinctive
cultural origin, but its underlying preoccupation with
human good makes it at bottom a moral issue in which Buddhism
and other religions have a legitimate stake. The Global
Ethic endorses the view that the principles it sets
forth on human rights are neither new nor "Western" when
it states: "We affirm that a common set of core values
is found in the teachings of the religions, and that these
form the basis of a global ethic." [64]
A
final thought. Above I have spoken only of human
rights, and in the context of Buddhism this perspective
may be unduly narrow in that it seems to preclude the
universe of sentient non-human beings from any entitlement
to rights. Buddhists may feel, therefore, that it is less
prejudicial in discussions of this kind to revert to the
older terminology of "natural" rights. Whether or not
animals have rights, and whether these are the same rights
as human beings, is a matter which requires separate discussion.
If human rights flow from human nature, as suggested,
it may be that rights of different kinds flow from natures
of different kinds. Such would seem to be the understanding
of classical Buddhism.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
de
Bary, W.Theodore (1988), "Neo-Confucianism and Human Rights,"
in Human Rights and the World's Religions, ed.
Leroy S. Rouner, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press,
pp. 183-198.
Bilimoria,
Purushottama (1993) "Is 'Adhikaara' good enough
for "rights"," Asian Philosophy 23, pp. 3-13.
Bradney,
A. (1993), Religions, Rights and Laws. Leicester:
Leicester University Press.
Carlyle,
R.W. and A.J. Carlyle (1950), A History of Medieval
Political Theory in the West. Edinburgh: Blackwood
and Sons.
Carrithers,
Michael. (1985), "An alternative social history of the
self," in The category of the person. Anthropology,
philosophy, history, eds. Carrithers, M, S. Collins,
and S. Lukes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp.
234-256.
Dagger,
Richard (1989), "Rights," in Political Innovation and
Conceptual Change, ed. et al Terence Ball, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 292-308.
Donnelly,
Jack (1985), The Concept of Human Rights. London
and Sydney: Croom Helm.
Finnis,
J.M. (1980), Natural Law and Natural Rights. Clarendon
Law Series, H.L.A. Hart, ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Harris,
Ian "Causation and Telos: The Problem of Buddhist Environmental
Ethics", Journal of Buddhist Ethics 1, pp.45-56.
Hohfeld,
Wesley (1964), Fundamental Legal Conceptions. New
Haven: Yale University Press.
Howard,
Rhoda (1986), "Is there an African concept of human rights?,"
in Foreign Policy and Human Rights, ed. R.J. Vincent,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 11-32.
Hsiung,
James C. (1985), Human Rights in East Asia: A Cultural
Perspective. New York: Paragon House.
Humana,
Charles (1992), World Human Rights Guide. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Inada,
Kenneth K. (1982), "The Buddhist Perspective on Human
Rights," in Human Rights in Religious Traditions,
ed. Arlene Swidler, New York: Pilgrims Press, pp. 66-76.
____
(1990), "A Buddhist Response to the Nature of Human Rights,"
in Asian Perspectives on Human Rights, eds. Claude
E. Welch Jr. and Virginia A. Leary, Boulder,Co: Westview
Press, pp. 91-103.
James,
Stephen A. (1994) "Reconciling International Human Rights
and Cultural Relativism: the case of female circumcision,"
Bioethics 8, pp. 1-26.
Keown,
Damien (1992), The Nature of Buddhist Ethics. London:
Macmillan.
Kung,
Hans and Karl-Josef Kuschel, eds. (1993), A Global
Ethic. The Declaration of the Parliament of the World's
Religions. London: SCM Press.
Kung,
Hans, Josef Van Ess, Heinrich Von Stietencron, and Heinz
Bechert (1986), Christianity and the World Religions,
second ed. London: SCM Press.
Ladd,
John, ed. (1983), Ethical Relativism. Lanham: University
Press of America.
Little,
David, John Kelsay, and Abdulaziz Sachedina, eds. (1988),
Human Rights and the Conflict of Cultures. Columbia,
S.C.: University of South Carolina Press.
MacIntyre,
Alasdair (1981), After Virtue. A Study in Moral Theory.
London: Duckworth.
Macy,
Joanna Rogers (1979) "Dependent Co-Arising: The Distinctiveness
of Buddhist Ethics," Journal of Religious Ethics
7, pp. 38-52.
Milne,
A.J.M. (1986), Human Rights and Human Diversity.
London: Macmillan.
Nickel,
James W. (1987), Making Sense of Human Rights.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Panikkar,
R. (1982) "Is the Notion of Human Rights a Western Concept?,"
Diogenes 120, pp. 75-102.
Perera,
L.H.H., ed. (1988), Human Rights and Religions in Sri
Lanka. A Commentary on the Universal Declaration of Human
Rights. Colombo:Sri Lanka Foundation.
Perera,
L.P.N. (1991), Buddhism and Human Rights. A Buddhist
Commentary on the Universal Declaration of Human Rights.
Colombo: Karunaratne and Sons.
Pollis,
Adamantia and Peter Schwab (1979), Human Rights: Cultural
and Ideological Perspectives. New York: Praeger.
Rouner,
Leroy S. (1988), Human Rights and the World's Religions
. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press.
de
Silva, K.M. et al., eds. (1988), Ethnic Conflict in
Buddhist Societies: Sri Lanka, Thailand and Burma.
Boulder,Co: Westview Press.
Stackhouse,
Max L. (1984), Creeds, Society, and Human Rights.
Grand Rapids, Michigan: William B.Eerdmans Publishing
Company.
Swidler,
Arlene, ed. (1982), Human Rights in Religious Traditions.
New York: Pilgrims Press.
Teson,
Fernando R. (1985) "International Human Rights and Cultural
Relativism," Virginia Journal of International Law
25, pp. 869- 898.
Tyagi,
Yogesh K. (1981) "Third World Response to Human Rights,"
Indian Journal of International Law 21, pp. 119-140.
Unno,
Taitetsu (1988), "Personal Rights and Contemporary Buddhism,"
in Human Rights in the World's Religions, ed. Leroy
S. Rouner, Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame
Press, pp. 129-147.
Vajiragnana,
Rev. (1992) "Justice in Buddhism," Vesak Sirisara
(unpaginated version from the Electronic Buddhist Archive).
Welch,
Claude .E. Jr. and V. Leary (1990), Asian Perspectives
on Human Rights. Boulder, Co: Westview Press.
NOTES
[1]
The text of the Declaration, along with commentaries and
supplementary information is available in Kung and Kuschel,
(eds) (1993). Return
[2]
Kung and Kuschel (eds) (1993:8). Return
[3]
For a range of cultural and ideological perspectives on
human rights see Pollis and Schwab (1979).Return
[4]
On the absence of ethics in Hinduism see Creel (1977:20ff).
Return
[5]
In spite of its contemporary importance, however, little
appears to have been written on the subject from a specifically
Buddhist perspective. The only monograph on the subject
appears to be Perera (1991), and I am grateful to the
Ven. Mahinda Deegalle for bringing it to my attention.
Panikkar (1982:76n) refers to a UNESCO Symposium which
took place in Bangkok in 1979 entitled Meeting of Experts
on the Place of Human Rights in Cultural and Religious
Traditions, which apparently included discussion of
Buddhism. I have as yet been unable to obtain a copy of
the Final Report SS-79/CONF. 607/10 of 6 February 1980.
Return
[6]
On the analogous question of whether there is an "African"
doctrine of human rights see Howard (1986). Return
[7]
For information on these empirical questions see Humana
(1992), Hsiung (1985), Rupesinghe et al (1993),
de Silva (1988), also Human Rights in Developing Countries,
Yearbook 1993 (Copenhagen, 1993: Nordic Human Rights Publications).
Return
[8]
Dagger (1989:293). I am indebted to Dagger's excellent
paper throughout this section. Return
[9]
Dagger (1989:294), original emphasis. Return
[10]
Finnis (1980:206). Return
[11]
Stackhouse lists five (1984:35ff). Little (1988) shows
the dependency of the modern Western secular and liberal
ideology on Christian theology by tracing the historical
connection between the Christian concept of conscience
and the intellectual framework within which the American
doctrines of liberty and religious freedom emerged in
the eighteenth century in the writings of Thomas Jefferson
and James Madison. He suggests that this Western framework
applies relatively unproblematically to Buddhism and Islam,
and notes in general: "Thus, current human rights formulations,
along with the important notions that underlie them, are
by no means necessarily irrelevant to cultures outside
the West" (1988:31). For perspectives on human rights
from the world's religions see Rouner (1988) and Swidler
(1982). Issues concerning religion and rights are discussed
by Bradney (1993). A commentary on the Universal Declaration
from the perspective of Buddhism, Hinduism, Christianity
and Islam may be found in Human Rights and Religions
in Sri Lanka, published by the Sri Lanka Foundation
(Colombo, 1988). The Buddhist commentary by Perera was
republished separately in 1991. Return
[12]
Stackhouse (1984:35) Return
[13]
Stackhouse (1984:36). Return
[14]
For a survey see Carlyle and Carlyle (1950) Return
[15]
Finnis (1980:208). Return
[16]
The most influential modern analysis of rights is that
by Hohfeld (1964). Return
[17]
Finnis (1980:199-205). Return
[18]
Finnis (1980:205), original emphasis. Return
[19]
Perera's discussion of Buddhism and human rights does
not address these questions, and seems to assume that
the concept of rights and human rights as understood in
the Universal Declaration are directly applicable to canonical
Buddhism. Return
[20]
For the view that moral values are determined by culture,
as maintained by many anthropologists, see Ladd (ed.)
(1983). The defensibility of a specific cultural custom
(female circumcision) from a human rights perspective
is discussed by James (1994). Return
[21]
Pali Text Society Pali-English Dictionary, uju
and ujju. Return
[22]
On the concept of rights in Hinduism and the meaning of
adhikaara, see Bilimoria (1993), also Creel (1977:19).
In Buddhist languages the notion of rights may be distributed
among a variety of terms, as perhaps, in Latin among the
words auctoritas, potestas, dominium, iurisdictio,
proprietas, libertas and ius (Dagger, 1989:291). Return
[23]
Quoted in Dagger (1989:286). Return
[24]
Finnis (1980:209). Return
[25]
Vajiragnana (1992) Return
[26]
See, for example, the Sigaalovaadasutta. Return
[27]
Dagger (1989:297) Return
[28]
Finnis (1980:209) Return
[29]
Finnis (1980:210) Return
[30]
MacIntyre (1981:69). Cf. de Bary on the Chinese neologisms
which have been coined to express these concepts (1988:183).
Return
[31]
The institution of caste is criticized in numerous early
discourses, notably the So.nada.n.dasutta. Return
[32]
Carrithers (1985) suggests that the Buddhist concept of
the "self" (which he relates to Mauss's concept of the
"moi") is one which is easily transportable across cultural
frontiers. This enhances the prospects for a Buddhist
doctrine of universal human rights. Return
[33]
Useful discussions of the philosophical basis of human
rights may be found in Donnelly (1985) and Nickel (1987).
Return
[34]
On how far the Western concept of human rights is relevant
or applicable to other cultures see Panikkar (1982), Teson
(1985), Milne (1986), Welch et al (1990). Return
[35]
Perera (1991:xi). Return
[36]
MacIntyre (1981:69). Return
[37]
A Global Ethic, p.14 Return
[38]
A Global Ethic, p.23 original emphasis.
Return
[39]
Kung (1986:383f), original emphasis. Return
[40]
A Global Ethic, p.62f Return
[41]
Inada (1982:71) Return
[42]
Inada (1982:70), paragraphs joined. Return
[43]
Inada (1982:70). Return
[44]
Inada (1982:70f). Return
[45]
An earlier attempt to ground Buddhist ethics in dependent-
origination can be found in Macy (1979). Macy offers the
Sarvodaya Shramadana, a self-help movement in Sri Lanka,
as "A notable example of the ethics of pa.ticca-samuppaada,"
but, like Inada, fails to explain how a moral imperative
arises out of this doctrine. Also drawn to the seemingly
magnetic doctrines of no-self and dependent-origination
is Taitetsu Unno, whose 1988 article, supposedly about
rights, is taken up almost entirely in providing a Pure
Land perspective on these two doctrines. While these doctrines
offer a congenial metaphysical backdrop for Buddhist ethics,
they cannot provide a moral ground for rights.
Harris (1994) expresses doubts that dependent-origination
can provide a satisfactory basis for Buddhist ecology.
Return
[46]
In a second essay on the subject (1990) Inada gives much
less emphasis to dependent-origination and seems to want
to ground human rights in compassion. However, the nature
of the argument, and in particular the concluding paragraph,
are far from clear. Return
[47]
Perera (1991:28, cf.88). Return
[48]
Perera (1991:29). Return
[49]
A further problem, although I believe it is ultimately
a pseudo- problem, is that Buddhism sees desire as the
cause of suffering. Desire would therefore seem an unlikely
foundation for human rights. Return
[50]
Perera (1991:28). Return
[51]
Article 1: "All human beings are born free and equal in
dignity and rights. They are endowed with reason and conscience
and should act towards one another in a spirit of brotherhood."
Return
[52]
Perera (1991:24). Return
[53]
A discussion of human nature and human good in Buddhism
will be found in my forthcoming Buddhism & Bioethics
(Macmillan, 1995). Return
[54]
A more familiar way of making the same point in Buddhist
terminology would be to say that all beings are potential
Buddhas or possess the "Buddha-nature." Return
[55]
Emphasis added. Return
[56]
Emphasis added. Return
[57]
In the view of Perera: "From the religious angle, it is
possible to state that in this Declaration lie enshrined
certain values and norms emphasized by the major religions
of the world. Though not directly expressed, the basic
principles of the Declaration are supported and reinforced
by these religious traditions, and among them the contribution
of the Buddhist tradition, to say the least, is quite
outstanding" (1991:xiii). Though not wishing to deny that
the early teachings support the principles of the Declaration,
I do not agree that the contribution of the Buddhist //tradition//
to the cause of human rights is in any way "outstanding."
Return
[58]
In certain areas (such as the prohibition on alcohol and
matters of sexual morality) the precepts go beyond the
more limited aims of human rights charters. This is because
Buddhism provides a particular vision of human good and
also defines the practices required for its fulfillment.
Return
[59]
Keown (1992:33). Return
[60]
Sometimes a contrast is drawn between the "voluntary"
nature of the Buddhist precepts and the "commandments"
of Christianity. While the format of the Buddhist precepts
is certainly more appealing to liberal tastes, the distinction
has little real meaning. The precepts apply whether or
not they are formally "undertaken," and are commandments
in all but name. Return
[61]
Kung and Kuschel (eds) (1993:104), original emphasis.
Return
[62]
Vajiragnana (1992). Return
[63]
A.iii.208 Return
[64]
Kung and Kuschel (eds) (1993:14). Return
http://jbe.la.psu.edu/index.html
Volume 2 1995