Attitudes to Euthanasia
in the Vinaya and Commentary
By Damien
Keown
Goldsmiths
College, University of London
Abstract
The
prohibition on taking human life is one of the cornerstones
of Buddhist ethics, but there is often confusion about the
interpretation of this prohibition in different contexts.
In his commentary on the third paaraajika in the Samantapaasaadikaa,
Buddhaghosa sets out to clarify the legal provisions of the
monastic precept against taking life. The root text and his
comments on it are relevant to the contemporary debate on
euthanasia, and this paper considers what light Buddhist jurisprudence
can shed on this moral dilemma.
The third
paaraajika is one of the four most serious monastic
offences that can be committed by a monk, and breaking any
one of them is punished by lifelong expulsion from the monastic
community. The four paaraajika offences are:
(1) Sexual
intercourse
(2) Stealing
(3) Taking life
(4) Falsely laying claim to superhuman powers.
These
four precepts are essentially a reformulation of what might
be called the four "core moral precepts" of Buddhism. Usually
they are found in the order 3-2-1-4 as in the Pa~ncasiila
or Five Precepts for laymen, as well as in other moral codes
like the Eight and Ten Precepts. In these formulations the
precept against taking life always comes first, so the order
in the monastic code is anomalous. What the monastic precept
prohibits specifically is killing something having human form
(manussaviggaha).
The prohibition
on taking human life is one of the cornerstones of Buddhist
ethics, but there is often confusion about the interpretation
of this precept in different contexts. In his Samantapaasaadikaa
commentary, Buddhaghosa sets out to clarify the legal provisions
of the precept. He discusses a variety of cases, real and
hypothetical, where death ensues, and endeavors to clarify
the legal requirements for a breach of the precept to have
taken place.
His casuistry
is an illuminating guide not just to monastic law but to the
wider moral issues surrounding the taking of life, and his
examples have relevance for a range of contemporary issues
relating to the law and ethics of medicine, such as suicide,
physician-assisted suicide, euthanasia, and abortion. In fact
of the sixty or so cases reported under this rubric in the
Vinaya about one-third are concerned with deaths that
occurred due to medical intervention of one kind or another.
The practice of medicine occupies an important place in the
discussion, no doubt because death often occurred in the context
of medical treatment administered by monks.
In commenting
on these cases, Buddhaghosa also devotes some time to discussing
routine issues which arise in medical practice -- such as
which classes of people should be taken on as patients and
which not -- and some of what he says would not be out of
place in a professional code of ethics such as that of the
AMA or the BMA. He also digresses to discuss issues such as
the therapeutic use of magical charms, a practice that may
bear more than a passing resemblance to the practice of physicians
today, particularly where the use of placebos is concerned.
Representatives
of the Buddhist tradition are rarely found at the cutting
edge of modern ethical debate, and it is often assumed that
early Buddhist literature has little to say about the kinds
of moral dilemmas that are debated in the modern world. This
is to overlook the fact that there are certain issues in the
practice of medicine that are perennial, and these issues
were faced by Buddhist monks who practiced as physicians from
the earliest times. The way the problems are formulated in
the Vinaya and commentary often differs from the way
they are presented today, and modern considerations often
give the issues a different nuance. Nevertheless, the early
sources can at least provide a useful starting point and direction
for reflection.
The central
legal concepts involved in Buddhaghosa's discussion are those
of method, intention, and agency. The methods of causing
death mentioned in the Vinaya are many and varied,
including the use of weapons, devices ranging from pits and
traps to more subtle psychological strategies like frightening
someone to death by dressing up as a ghost, and, of course,
death resulting from unsuccessful medical treatments. In terms
of intention, the examples show that guilt is firmly
tied to the mens rea or state of mind of the accused
at the time the offence was committed. Guilt or innocence
depends upon the outcome tallying with the intention with
which one undertook the project in question. The concept of
agency is important where other parties are involved
as intermediaries, as when one monk instructs another to carry
out a lethal plan. These notions serve as the pegs on which
Buddhaghosa hangs his discussion, the overall purpose of which
is to establish in what circumstances a monk is guilty of
an offence and the grade of punishment appropriate.
The Vinaya
consists of a complex blend of moral and legal issues, and
I should make clear that my primary interest is in the moral
principles rather than the legal ones. Unfortunately, ethical
discourse did not reach the same degree of sophistication
or precision in the early texts as legal terminology. We therefore
have no option but to rely on the discussions of the vinayadharas.
My hope is that it is possible from their discussions to isolate
principles which can then be applied outside of the specific
context and jurisdiction of the Vinaya. Care must be
taken here, however, since just because something is prohibited
by the Vinaya does not mean it is immoral. The sources
themselves make a distinction between pa.n.natti-vajja
-- or what is prohibited by the Vinaya (for example,
eating after midday) -- and what is lokavajja, or regarded
as immoral by the world at large outside the cloister (for
example, killing, stealing, and lying). Furthermore, many
rules in the Vinaya were inserted simply to satisfy
the expectations of the laity so that Buddhist monks would
not seem less scrupulous than their religious competitors.
Despite
the fact that the Vinaya is also concerned with the
sub-moral duties of ecclesiastical office, however, certain
sections of it, such as the third paaraajika, do address
issues which are primarily of a moral nature, and the prohibition
on taking life comes into this category. As already mentioned,
it is found in every formulation of Buddhist precepts, whether
intended for laity or monks.
The commentary
to the third paaraajika begins with the unlikely topic
of meditation, and in particular a specific form of meditation
known as "contemplation of the impure." This is a method used
to counteract attachment. In practicing it one might reflect
upon the body as impermanent, a thing subject to decay and
corruption, and not a proper object of attachment. Having
instructed the monks on this theme, the Buddha retired into
seclusion for a fortnight. Unfortunately, the monks became
overzealous in their practice and developed disgust and loathing
for their bodies. So intense did this become that many felt
death would be preferable to such a repulsive existence. Accordingly,
they proceeded to kill themselves, and lent assistance to
one another in doing so. They found a willing assistant in
the form of Migala.n.dika, a "sham recluse" (sama.na-kuttaka),
who agreed to assist by killing the monks in return for their
robes and bowls. Migala.n.dika dispatched his victims with
a large knife, but halfway through the bloody process suffered
a bout of remorse. At this point a devil appeared and whispered
reassuringly in his ear that by "bringing across those who
had not yet crossed" he was in fact doing right. In other
words, by killing the monks he was saving them from the sufferings
of sa.msaara. Reassured by this Migala.n.dika resumed
his work and killed a large number of monks, up to sixty on
a single day.
When the
Buddha came out of his fortnight's seclusion he noticed the
drop in numbers among the monks and inquired as to the cause.
When he learned what had taken place he proclaimed the third
of the four most serious monastic offences (paaraajika).
This is the prohibition on taking human life, and was announced
as follows:
Whatever
monk should intentionally deprive a human being of life,
or should look about to be his knife-bringer, he is also
one who is defeated and is no more in communion.(1)
In connection
with euthanasia it will be seen from the context that this
precept prohibits killing even when the person being killed
requests assistance in dying. The phrase "should look about
to be his knife-bringer" (sattahaaraka.m vaassa pariyeseyya)
is a clear reference to the part played in this episode by
Migala.n.dika. Migala.n.dika, it will be noted, was doing
little more than acting as the instrument of execution: it
was the monks themselves who wished to die, and indeed offered
Migala.n.dika their robes and bowls as an inducement for his
help. Nevertheless, the role of "knife-bringer" or "knife-bearer"(2)
is specifically singled out for condemnation in the precept.
The specific ground for the proclamation of the third paaraajika
was thus what today might be termed the practice of voluntary
active euthanasia.
One of
the main arguments advanced in favor of allowing euthanasia
in the contemporary debate is respect for autonomy. This is
founded on the twin claims that the free choices of rational
individuals should be respected, and that all individuals
have the right to dispose of their lives as they see fit.
This ground would seem applicable to the present case. The
monks were, as far as we can tell, competent rational adults.
They wished to die because they had made the judgement that
their lives were "not worth living" and that they would be
"better off dead." This was a free choice consequent upon
their evaluation of their quality of life, which they deemed
to be insufficient to justify continued existence. In terms
of respect for autonomy, therefore, their decision might be
thought justifiable, in the sense that as competent adults
it was up to them to dispose of their lives as they saw fit.
It seems, however, that the Buddha rejected this line of argument.
Could
it be, perhaps, that the monastic prohibition was introduced
not as a matter of principle, but simply because the monks
in this case were suffering from religious zeal and had not
allowed time for sober consideration of their decision? Perhaps
if they had expressed a repeated and sustained wish over time
to end their lives, the Buddha would have allowed it. This
we cannot know, but such an interpretation is unlikely, if
for no other reason than that the rule imposes not just a
cooling off period before execution is allowed but an absolute
prohibition.
After
this first formulation of the precept a short episode is narrated
that leads to the precept being expanded to include not just
killing but also incitement to death. The text relates how
a group of wicked monks became enamoured of the wife of a
layman. In order to weaken his attachment to life and get
him out of the way, the monks spoke to the husband of the
pleasures that would be his reward in heaven for having lived
a life of virtue:
Layman,
you have done what is right, done what is virtuous, gained
security from fear. You have not done evil, you have not
been cruel, you have not been violent. You have done good
and abstained from evil. What need have you of this evil,
difficult life? Death would be better for you than life.
Hereafter, when you die, when your body is destroyed at
death, you will pass to a happy bourn, to a heaven world.
There, possessed of and provided with five divine qualities
of sensual pleasure, you will amuse yourself.(3)
As a result
of hearing this the husband began to eat and drink the wrong
kind of food and eventually succumbed to a fatal illness.
When the matter was reported to the Buddha he expelled the
monks and expanded the definition of the third paaraajika
to include incitement to death:
Should
any monk intentionally deprive a human being of life or
look about so as to be his knife-bringer, or eulogize death,
or incite [anyone] to death saying "My good man,
what need have you of this evil, difficult life? Death would
be better for you than life," -- or who should deliberately
and purposefully in various ways eulogize death or incite
anyone] to death: he is also one who is defeated, he
is not in communion.(4)
This amplification
of the scope of the precept is particularly important in the
context of euthanasia since the weight of the case for allowing
euthanasia rests on the postulate that "death would be better
than life," especially when, to use the wording of the precept,
life seems "evil and difficult."
Apart
from respect for autonomy, a second consideration sometimes
advanced in support of euthanasia is compassion. Compassion
is of great importance in Buddhism, particularly when linked
to the notion of the bodhisattva. Some later sources reveal
an increasing awareness of how a commitment to the alleviation
of suffering on the part of a bodhisattva can create a conflict
with the principle of the inviolability of life. Compassion,
for example, might lead one to take life in order to alleviate
suffering, and indeed this is the second main ground on which
euthanasia is advocated today. Such a situation is addressed
in the Vinaya, in the first of the sixty or so cases
to be reported after the precept against killing was declared.(5)
This case involves a conflict between the prohibition on taking
life and the compassionate desire to alleviate suffering.
The case is stated in just a couple of lines:
At that
time a certain monk was ill. Out of compassion the other
monks spoke favorably to him of death. The monk died.
Fortunately,
the commentary expands on this rather terse account:
"Out
of compassion" means that those monks, seeing the great
pain the monk was in from the illness felt compassion and
said to him: "You are a virtuous man and have performed
good deeds, why should you be afraid of dying? Indeed, heaven
is assured for a virtuous man at the very instant of death."
Thus they made death their aim and...spoke in favor of death.
That monk, as a result of them speaking favorably of death,
ceased to take food and shortly after died. It was because
of this that they committed an offence.(6)
It is
noteworthy that those found guilty did not go so far as to
actually administer euthanasia, but only suggested to the
dying monk that he would be "better off dead." The monk himself
then ceased to take food and died, so technically their offence
was incitement to suicide. Despite their benevolent motive,
namely that a terminal patient should be spared unnecessary
pain, the judgement was that those involved were guilty of
a breach of the precept. According to Buddhaghosa, the essence
of their wrongdoing was that the guilty monks made death
their aim (mara.naatthika). This suggests that
to make death one's aim, to will death, and a fortiori
to embark on any course with death as one's purpose, goal
or outcome, regardless of how benevolent the motive, is immoral
from a Buddhist perspective.(7)
In a modern context, this prohibition would seem to include
anyone who aids or abets suicide, lends help in the context
of assisted suicide or, of course, administers euthanasia
directly. Although compassion is a common motive it does not
here provide exoneration. From this we may conclude that while
compassion should accompany moral acts it does not
justify them, and that compassion is a virtue only
when the end it seeks is good.
A handful
of other cases are reported which have a bearing on our theme.
In one case a monk, perhaps again motivated by compassion,
appeals for the swift execution of a criminal:
At that
time a certain monk, having gone to the place of execution,
said to the executioner, "Sir, do not keep him in misery.
By one blow deprive him of life." "Very well, your Reverence,"
said he, and by one blow deprived him of life.(8)
The monk's
motive, apparently, was to spare the prisoner the mental distress
of having to wait for the appointed time of execution. The
prisoner was to have been killed anyway, and the monk's intervention
simply brought forward the inevitable outcome. In spite of
his desire to spare the prisoner suffering, the monk was nevertheless
found guilty of a breach of the precept.
The final
case I will mention concerns a monk who assists in bringing
about the death of an invalid by prescribing a drink that
will be fatal for him:
At one
time a certain man whose hands and feet had been cut off
was in the paternal home surrounded by relations. A certain
monk said to these people, "Reverend sirs, do you desire
his death?" "Indeed, honored sir, we do desire it," they
said. "Then you should make him drink buttermilk," he said.
They made him drink buttermilk and he died.(9)
The reason
why the relatives desired the death of the patient is not
made clear. The circumstances were that an individual had
suffered amputation of the hands and feet. A person in this
condition would be able to do little for himself and would
require constant attention and care. The family expressed
the opinion that it would be better if the man died. This
may have been because they judged his quality of life to be
so poor that he would be "better off dead." Perhaps their
motive was simply to be free of the burden of providing the
care and attention he required. It may even have been a combination
of these reasons. We are not told if the patient agreed with
the view of his family that he should die. It may be that
the man's view about his death is not reported because it
is not thought relevant, since intentional killing is judged
wrong regardless of whether the victim consents or not. The
circumstances thus suggest this was a case of active euthanasia,
although it is not clear whether it was voluntary or not.
In the event, the monk who gave the advice was excommunicated.
A similar verdict was pronounced in the case of a nun who
recommended a concoction of "salted sour gruel" (lo.nasuviiraka)
as a means of causing the death of another patient in the
same condition.(10)
At one
point in his commentary Buddhaghosa has a brief but interesting
discussion about the situation of terminally ill patients
which at first sight seems to suggest that euthanasia may
be allowable in certain circumstances. This discussion occurs
in the context of a somewhat bizarre case of a monk who was
deeply depressed and threw himself off Vulture's Peak, apparently
with the intention of committing suicide. By chance he happened
to fall on top of a basket-maker who was under the precipice
at that time. Miraculously the monk survived but the basket
maker tragically died. After discussing this case Buddhaghosa
mentions three interesting scenarios relating to dying patients.
This is what he says:
You
should not kill yourself by throwing yourself off a cliff,
nor by any other method even down to withdrawal from food.
If one who is sick ceases to take food with the intention
of dying when medicine and nursing care are at hand, he
commits a dukka.ta. But in the case of a patient
who has suffered a long time with a serious illness the
nursing monks may become weary and turn away in despair
thinking "when will we ever cure him of this illness?" Here
it is legitimate to decline food and medical care if the
patient sees that the monks are worn out and his life cannot
be prolonged even with intensive care.(11)
There
would seem to be a contrast here between the case of a person
who rejects medical care with the express purpose of ending
his life, and one who resigns himself to the inevitability
of death after treatment has failed and the medical resources
have been exhausted. The moral distinction is that the first
patient seeks death or "makes death his aim," to use Buddhaghosa's
phrase, while the second simply accepts the inevitability
and proximity of death and rejects further treatment or nourishment
as pointless. The first person wishes to die; the second person
wishes to live. The second person, however, is resigned to
the fact that he is beyond medical help and therefore declines
further medical intervention.
This example
suggests that Buddhism does not believe there is a moral obligation
to preserve life at all costs or to eke out a life that is
spent. Recognizing the inevitability of death, of course,
is a central element in Buddhist teachings. Death cannot be
prevented forever, and Buddhists are encouraged to be mindful
and prepared for the evil hour when it comes. To seek to prolong
life beyond its natural span by recourse to ever more elaborate
technology when no cure or recovery is in sight is to live
in a state of denial of the realities of human life. The Buddha
himself declined to extend his life, although he reports that
this option was open to him. Accordingly, in terms of the
Vinaya, it would seem justifiable to refuse piecemeal
medical treatments that do nothing more than postpone the
inevitable for a short time. It should be noted that although
this is sometimes described as "passive euthanasia" this is
a misnomer, since there is only euthanasia when death is willed
directly as a means or an end.
Buddhaghosa
goes on to give two further examples of death involving religious
practice that do not breach the third paaraajika.
It is
also legitimate in the case of one who suffering from a
painful illness from which he knows he will not recover
withdraws from food in the knowledge that he is on the brink
of a spiritual breakthrough. Again, this time in the context
of meditation, it legitimate for one who is not ill but
who inspired by religious feeling concludes that the search
for food is burdensome, withdraws from it and exerts himself
in his meditation subject.(12)
The third
example is similar to the second, except that this time the
patient has the added incentive that he may at this late stage
in his life make a spiritual leap forward if he applies all
his remaining efforts to meditation.
The final
example is slightly unusual in that the subject is not sick
at all. Instead, full of religious zeal (sa.mvega),
he wishes to devote himself solely to meditation. Buddhaghosa
does not make clear whether this is undertaken by way of a
fast unto death, as in the Jain practice of sallekhanaa,
or is simply a temporary fast. If it is the former, and is
undertaken by a young person in good health, some may feel
that it is morally culpable in endangering life unnecessarily
and is not in keeping with the principle of the "middle way."
What conclusions
can be drawn from the Vinaya and Buddhaghosa's commentary?
(1) The
Vinaya is a particularly important source for Buddhist
ethics because ethico-legal issues receive a more detailed
analysis in the Vinaya than in either the Sutta-Pi.taka
or the Abhidhamma. The casuistry employed suggests
parallels with Western moral philosophy, which often uses
scenarios and hypothetical cases in an attempt to extract
moral principles from different practical contexts. The sources
reveal that, contrary to what is often asserted by Western
commentators, early Buddhism does take a clear and defensible
stand on controversial moral questions. This position, perhaps
not unsurprisingly, turns out to be a conservative one.
(2) Although
discussed in the context of monastic law, it seems fair to
see the law here as defending what is fundamentally a moral
value. In other words taking human life -- even one's own
life -- seems to be wrong not because one is wearing an orange
robe but because in the view of the texts the destruction
of life is intrinsically immoral whether done by monk or layman.
(3) With
respect to euthanasia, it would seem to be wrong to commit
suicide; wrong to act as "knife-bringer" to someone seeking
death; wrong to emphasize the positive aspects of death and
the negative aspects of life; wrong to incite someone to kill
another, and wrong to assist others in causing death. While
we might wish for more detail in the individual five or so
cases relating to euthanasia, they all seem to suggest that
it is immoral to affirm that death is better than life.
(4) The
prohibition on euthanasia does not imply a commitment to vitalism,
namely the doctrine that life should be prolonged at all costs.
Withdrawal from food and refusal of medical intervention when
the end is night is not seen as immoral, since this is to
do no more than accept death as an inevitable part of life.
(5) Finally,
the views that are expressed in the texts are one thing. The
importance that should be attached to the texts as sources
for resolving moral dilemmas is another. It is possible to
put forward the argument, for instance, that since these texts
are embedded in a particular cultural and historical framework
they have little relevance to modern Western societies. On
the other hand, it may be felt that the views expressed in
canonical texts should not lightly be set aside, and should
at least be the point of departure for reflection on contemporary
moral problems.
Notes
1.
Vin.iii.70. Return to text
2.
On the analysis of this term see VA.ii.441. Return
to text
3.
Vin.iii.71. Return to text
4.
Vin.iii.72. Return to text
5.
Vin ii.79. Return to text
6.
VA.ii.464. Return to text
7.
I believe this also applies in cases of "arhat suicide," an
issue I have discussed elsewhere. See "Buddhism and Suicide:
The Case of Channa," Journal
of Buddhist Ethics, Vol. 3, 1996, pp. 8-31. Return
to text
8.
Vin.iii.85. Return to text
9.
Vin.iii.85. Return to text
10.
Vin.iii.85. Return to text
11.
VA.ii.467. Return to text
12.
VA.ii.467. Return to text
http://jbe.la.psu.edu/index.html
Volume 6 1999
|